Base rate fallacy

Base rate fallacy, also called base rate neglect or base rate bias, is a formal fallacy. If presented with related base rate information (i.e. generic, general information) and specific information (information only pertaining to a certain case), the mind tends to ignore the former and focus on the latter.[1]

Base rate neglect is a specific form of the more general Extension neglect.

Examples

Example 1

A group of policemen have breathalyzers displaying false drunkenness in 5% of the cases in which the driver is sober. However, the breathalyzers never fail to detect a truly drunk person. One in a thousand drivers is driving drunk. Suppose the policemen then stop a driver at random, and force the driver to take a breathalyzer test. It indicates that the driver is drunk. We assume you don't know anything else about him or her. How high is the probability he or she really is drunk?

Many would answer as high as 0.95, but the correct probability is about 0.02.

To find the correct answer, one should use Bayes's theorem. The goal is to find the probability that the driver is drunk given that the breathalyzer indicated he/she is drunk, which can be represented as

where "D" means that the breathalyzer indicates that the driver is drunk. Bayes's theorem tells us that

We were told the following in the first paragraph:

As you can see from the formula, one needs p(D) for Bayes' theorem, which one can compute from the preceding values using

which gives

Plugging these numbers into Bayes' theorem, one finds that

A more intuitive explanation: on average, for every 1,000 drivers tested,

Therefore, the probability that one of the drivers among the 1 + 49.95 = 50.95 positive test results really is drunk is .

The validity of this result does, however, hinge on the validity of the initial assumption that the policeman stopped the driver truly at random, and not because of bad driving. If that or another non-arbitrary reason for stopping the driver was present, then the calculation also involves the probability of a drunk driver driving competently and a non-drunk driver driving (in-)competently.

Example 2

In a city of 1 million inhabitants let there be 100 terrorists and 999,900 non-terrorists. To simplify the example, it is assumed that all people present in the city are inhabitants. Thus, the base rate probability of a randomly selected inhabitant of the city being a terrorist is 0.0001, and the base rate probability of that same inhabitant being a non-terrorist is 0.9999. In an attempt to catch the terrorists, the city installs an alarm system with a surveillance camera and automatic facial recognition software.

The software has two failure rates of 1%:

Suppose now that an inhabitant triggers the alarm. What is the chance that the person is a terrorist? In other words, what is P(T | B), the probability that a terrorist has been detected given the ringing of the bell? Someone making the 'base rate fallacy' would infer that there is a 99% chance that the detected person is a terrorist. Although the inference seems to make sense, it is actually bad reasoning, and a calculation below will show that the chances he/she is a terrorist are actually near 1%, not near 99%.

The fallacy arises from confusing the natures of two different failure rates. The 'number of non-bells per 100 terrorists' and the 'number of non-terrorists per 100 bells' are unrelated quantities. One does not necessarily equal the other, and they don't even have to be almost equal. To show this, consider what happens if an identical alarm system were set up in a second city with no terrorists at all. As in the first city, the alarm sounds for 1 out of every 100 non-terrorist inhabitants detected, but unlike in the first city, the alarm never sounds for a terrorist. Therefore, 100% of all occasions of the alarm sounding are for non-terrorists, but a false negative rate cannot even be calculated. The 'number of non-terrorists per 100 bells' in that city is 100, yet P(T | B) = 0%. There is zero chance that a terrorist has been detected given the ringing of the bell.

Imagine that the first city's entire population of one million people pass in front of the camera. About 99 of the 100 terrorists will trigger the alarm—and so will about 9,999 of the 999,900 non-terrorists. Therefore, about 10,098 people will trigger the alarm, among which about 99 will be terrorists. So, the probability that a person triggering the alarm actually is a terrorist, is only about 99 in 10,098, which is less than 1%, and very, very far below our initial guess of 99%.

The base rate fallacy is so misleading in this example because there are many more non-terrorists than terrorists.

Findings in psychology

In experiments, people have been found to prefer individuating information over general information when the former is available.[2][3][4]

In some experiments, students were asked to estimate the grade point averages (GPAs) of hypothetical students. When given relevant statistics about GPA distribution, students tended to ignore them if given descriptive information about the particular student, even if the new descriptive information was obviously of little or no relevance to school performance.[3] This finding has been used to argue that interviews are an unnecessary part of the college admissions process because interviewers are unable to pick successful candidates better than basic statistics.

Psychologists Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky attempted to explain this finding in terms of a simple rule or "heuristic" called representativeness. They argued that many judgments relating to likelihood, or to cause and effect, are based on how representative one thing is of another, or of a category.[3] Kahneman considers base rate neglect to be a specific form of extension neglect.[5] Richard Nisbett has argued that some attributional biases like the fundamental attribution error are instances of the base rate fallacy: people do not use the "consensus information" (the "base rate") about how others behaved in similar situations and instead prefer simpler dispositional attributions.[6]

There is considerable debate in psychology on the conditions under which people do or do not appreciate base rate information.[7][8] Researchers in the heuristics-and-biases program have stressed empirical findings showing that people tend to ignore base rates and make inferences that violate certain norms of probabilistic reasoning, such as Bayes' theorem. The conclusion drawn from this line of research was that human probabilistic thinking is fundamentally flawed and error-prone.[9] Other researchers have emphasized the link between cognitive processes and information formats, arguing that such conclusions are not generally warranted.[10][11]

Consider again Example 1 from above. The required inference is to estimate the (posterior) probability that a (randomly picked) driver is drunk, given that the breathalyzer test is positive. Formally, this probability can be calculated using Bayes' theorem, as shown above. However, there are different ways of presenting the relevant information. Consider the following, formally equivalent variant of the problem:

 1 out of 1000 drivers are driving drunk. The breathalyzers never fail to detect a truly drunk person. For 50 out of the 999 drivers who are not drunk the breathalyzer falsely displays drunkness. Suppose the policemen then stop a driver at random, and force them to take a breathalyzer test. It indicates that he or she is drunk. We assume you don't know anything else about him or her. How high is the probability he or she really is drunk?

In this case, the relevant numerical information—p(drunk), p(D | drunk), p(D | sober)—is presented in terms of natural frequencies with respect to a certain reference class (see reference class problem). Empirical studies show that people's inferences correspond more closely to Bayes' rule when information is presented this way, helping to overcome base-rate neglect in laypeople[11] and experts.[12] As a consequence, organizations like the Cochrane Collaboration recommend using this kind of format for communicating health statistics.[13] Teaching people to translate these kinds of Bayesian reasoning problems into natural frequency formats is more effective than merely teaching them to plug probabilities (or percentages) into Bayes' theorem.[14] It has also been shown that graphical representations of natural frequencies (e.g., icon arrays) help people to make better inferences.[14][15][16]

Why are natural frequency formats helpful? One important reason is that this information format facilitates the required inference because it simplifies the necessary calculations. This can be seen when using an alternative way of computing the required probability p(drunk|D):

where N(drunk D) denotes the number of drivers that are drunk and get a positive breathalyzer result, and N(D) denotes the total number of cases with a positive breathalyzer result. The equivalence of this equation to the above one follows from the axioms of probability theory, according to which N(drunk D) = N × p (D | drunk) × p (drunk). Importantly, although this equation is formally equivalent to Bayes’ rule, it is not psychologically equivalent. Using natural frequencies simplifies the inference because the required mathematical operation can be performed on natural numbers, instead of normalized fractions (i.e., probabilities), because it makes the high number of false positives more transparent, and because natural frequencies exhibit a "nested-set structure".[17][18]

It is important to note that not any kind of frequency format facilitates Bayesian reasoning.[18][19] Natural frequencies refer to frequency information that results from natural sampling,[20] which preserves base rate information (e.g., number of drunken drivers when taking a random sample of drivers). This is different from systematic sampling, in which base rates are fixed a priori (e.g., in scientific experiments). In the latter case it is not possible to infer the posterior probability p (drunk | positive test) from comparing the number of drivers who are drunk and test positive compared to the total number of people who get a positive breathalyzer result, because base rate information is not preserved and must be explicitly re-introduced using Bayes' theorem.

See also

References list

  1. "Logical Fallacy: The Base Rate Fallacy". Fallacyfiles.org. Retrieved 2013-06-15.
  2. Bar-Hillel, Maya (1980). "The base-rate fallacy in probability judgments". Acta Psychologica. 44: 211–233. doi:10.1016/0001-6918(80)90046-3.
  3. 1 2 3 Kahneman, Daniel; Amos Tversky (1973). "On the psychology of prediction". Psychological Review. 80: 237–251. doi:10.1037/h0034747.
  4. Kahneman, Daniel; Amos Tversky (1985). "Evidential impact of base rates". In Daniel Kahneman, Paul Slovic & Amos Tversky (Eds.). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. pp. 153–160.
  5. Kahneman, Daniel (2000). "Evaluation by moments, past and future". In Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky (Eds.). Choices, Values and Frames.
  6. Nisbett, Richard E.; E. Borgida; R. Crandall; H. Reed (1976). "Popular induction: Information is not always informative". In J. S. Carroll & J. W. Payne (Eds.). Cognition and social behavior. 2. pp. 227–236.
  7. Koehler, J. J. (2010). "The base rate fallacy reconsidered: Descriptive, normative, and methodological challenges". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 19: 1. doi:10.1017/S0140525X00041157.
  8. Barbey, A. K.; Sloman, S. A. (2007). "Base-rate respect: From ecological rationality to dual processes". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 30 (3): 241–54; discussion 255–97. doi:10.1017/S0140525X07001653. PMID 17963533.
  9. Tversky, A.; Kahneman, D. (1974). "Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases". Science. 185 (4157): 1124–1131. doi:10.1126/science.185.4157.1124. PMID 17835457.
  10. Cosmides, Leda; John Tooby (1996). "Are humans good intuitive statisticians after all? Rethinking some conclusions of the literature on judgment under uncertainty". Cognition. 58: 1–73. doi:10.1016/0010-0277(95)00664-8.
  11. 1 2 Gigerenzer, G.; Hoffrage, U. (1995). "How to improve Bayesian reasoning without instruction: Frequency formats". Psychological Review. 102 (4): 684. doi:10.1037/0033-295X.102.4.684.
  12. Hoffrage, U.; Lindsey, S.; Hertwig, R.; Gigerenzer, G. (2000). "MEDICINE: Communicating Statistical Information". Science. 290 (5500): 2261–2262. doi:10.1126/science.290.5500.2261. PMID 11188724.
  13. Akl, E. A.; Oxman, A. D.; Herrin, J.; Vist, G. E.; Terrenato, I.; Sperati, F.; Costiniuk, C.; Blank, D.; Schünemann, H. (2011). Schünemann, Holger, ed. "Using alternative statistical formats for presenting risks and risk reductions". The Cochrane Library. doi:10.1002/14651858.CD006776.pub2.
  14. 1 2 Sedlmeier, P.; Gigerenzer, G. (2001). "Teaching Bayesian reasoning in less than two hours". Journal of Experimental Psychology: General. 130 (3): 380. doi:10.1037/0096-3445.130.3.380.
  15. Brase, G. L. (2009). "Pictorial representations in statistical reasoning". Applied Cognitive Psychology. 23 (3): 369–381. doi:10.1002/acp.1460.
  16. Edwards, A.; Elwyn, G.; Mulley, A. (2002). "Explaining risks: Turning numerical data into meaningful pictures". BMJ. 324 (7341): 827–830. doi:10.1136/bmj.324.7341.827. PMC 1122766Freely accessible. PMID 11934777.
  17. Girotto, V.; Gonzalez, M. (2001). "Solving probabilistic and statistical problems: A matter of information structure and question form". Cognition. 78 (3): 247–276. doi:10.1016/S0010-0277(00)00133-5. PMID 11124351.
  18. 1 2 Hoffrage, U.; Gigerenzer, G.; Krauss, S.; Martignon, L. (2002). "Representation facilitates reasoning: What natural frequencies are and what they are not". Cognition. 84 (3): 343–352. doi:10.1016/S0010-0277(02)00050-1. PMID 12044739.
  19. Gigerenzer, G.; Hoffrage, U. (1999). "Overcoming difficulties in Bayesian reasoning: A reply to Lewis and Keren (1999) and Mellers and McGraw (1999)". Psychological Review. 106 (2): 425. doi:10.1037/0033-295X.106.2.425.
  20. Kleiter, G. D. (1994). "Natural Sampling: Rationality without Base Rates". Contributions to Mathematical Psychology, Psychometrics, and Methodology. Recent Research in Psychology. pp. 375–388. doi:10.1007/978-1-4612-4308-3_27. ISBN 978-0-387-94169-1.

External links

This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the 11/27/2016. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.